ASEBL Journal Volume 10, Number 1 | Page 54

ASEBL Journal – Volume 10 Issue 1, January 2014 will look ahead to extraordinary gains and so default on any agreement (191). Nevertheless, we all seem to be programmed not only to be fair but to be generous – since we expect to be so treated; but paradoxically fairness is rooted in self-interest (201). Such social interactions depend on theory of mind (nonverbal), which in turn depends on a brain very different from that of a chimpanzee or our own ancient ancestors. We are able to detect deception quite well. The human brain has more than doubled in size over about 1 million years compared with that of a chimpanzee’s. Pagel suggests that the rapid development of our brain (in quality and not just quantity – on average Neanderthals had slightly larger brains) explains our survival over all others (251). The human brain is a super-charged version of Darwin’s descent with modification. (Some of the more interesting parts are when Pagel discusses Human Accelerated Regions – 49 in our genome, especially influential in neurons – and socalled junk DNA.) Much of our cooperative behaviors are a direct result of language, the ability to navigate multi-party transactions. Although we believe that homo ergaster had very rudimentary speech followed by more advanced speech in late homo erectus (the larynx), Pagel insists that only our species produced language (at most 200, 000 years ago) because of “social complexity” and as a “trait for promoting cooperation . . .” (279, 281). As others (Dunbar) have pointed out, Pagel notes that we use language (across the globe in 7,000 current forms) not just to speak but “principally to talk about each other . . .” (294), and this is reflected in key sounds and word lengths universal for thousands of years. In his discussion of free will (and returning to the function of consciousness as a cultural operator), Pagel says that our brains work out patterns ahead of schedule so that the subconscious might already know what to do in certain instances. This is relevant since our culturally-hungry brains are always in operation mode, as if on a sixth sense. Relatedly, an older part of our brain (affective) responds instinctually to highly charged moral situations – do no harm (329). Clearly, such social sensitivity has become over time a key cultural ingredient. Interestingly, though, Pagel (citing Daryl Bem) suggests that we do not know ourselves because of “introspection” but because of “observing our own behaviors . . .” – and why we often do not know how we would react in a hypothetical situation (327). Pagel goes on to say that consciousness is little more than an after effect (of a highly active brain) organizing input (332) – there might be something illusory about what we label “I.” Yet Pagel does not seem to be hinting at cultural determinism or the standard social science model in learning; rather, he seems to suggest that in order for us to imitate and improve upon behaviors (the cultural tools that have preserved our species), our brains need to catalogue (seamlessly) various strands of information in advance of our conscious processing such information. Finally, coming back to social learning and our ability (need) to connect in clusters, Pagel notes that in spite of our near obscurity in large cities (some of which date back almost 8,000 years), Stanley Milgrim’s six degrees of separation (i.e., our proximity to others) is valid, and, social viscosity, where we form small groups and stay close by (i.e., “social rules”) has not changed much over our long evolutionary history (365, 367). - Gregory F. Tague ▬ 54