ASEBL Journal Volume 10, Number 1 | Page 53

ASEBL Journal – Volume 10 Issue 1, January 2014 our predecessors roamed the globe and adapted (physically, genetically) to the new environments, but it was culture that initially propelled them (47) and subsequently sustained them to form complex social divisions of labor and societies. There is, of course, an advantage to different cultural groups: the passing down of rights and property (an advanced development), and hence why, Pagel suggests, there are many different cultures. “Cultures restrict the flow of genes” (54) and so, in spite of one homo sapiens sapiens species we all look ethnically different (in our ancestors’ predilections for selecting certain features). Just as we see in natural biology (RNA strands joining, hungry amoebae forming a spore tower to sacrifice many to save a few, the many cells and organs of the human body), “natural selection made it possible for individuals to align their interests with those of their group” (72), and indeed there are cues to which we respond positively when identifying who is part of our group and negatively when noting who is outside of the group. While Pagel stresses over and again the importance of the group in terms of culture, he does not minimize self-interest – “natural selection has duped us with an emotion that encourages group thinking” (98). Regarding cultural evolution and social learning (or what biologists call diversifying selection), the “variety” of individual skills and talents count most (100). Culture is a sorting process, says Pagel (131): someone makes a musical instrument, and then someone else begins to play it (109). Pagel makes a sustained argument for diverse cultural groups (human culture), but this development can only come to pass through distinct individuals. Oddly, high heritability (individual differences) has little to do with overall human survival (118); but yet natural selection would then have eliminated our differences. Pagel seems to suggest that there is an evolutionary bias for a variety of personality types. Likewise, Pagel says that the arts and religion are “cultural enhancers” – emotional motivators related to behavior (135). He seems satisfied with the simpler notions that the arts transmit ideas and that religion helps explain occurrences. Is this a bit perplexing? Pagel is arguing that we survived and thrived because of culture, but he does not quite come out and argue for an adaptive function in the arts (and lumps arts together without distinguishing one from another). Or maybe he does argue for an adaptive function. Even if beliefs are wrong, false, or incorrect they might, nonetheless, help a group survive (as D.S. Wilson has noted). Be that as it may, Pagel says that even without religion we would be much the same (i.e., selfish and morally corruptible). Simply, we have concocted religion to offer ourselves “courage and hope” and to coordinate and unite groups over other groups (159). As natural selection pits genes against genes, so religion induces emotions shared in a group (opposed to another) in “cultural relatedness” (165). However, there is no cycle (typically) of endless conflict; in fact, conflicts can render “opportunities” that produce moral outcomes (180-181). There are many distinct cultural groups with different beliefs (though all with one common denominator, the need, apparently, to own beliefs). With acknowledgment to Robert Trivers, Pagel notes that reciprocal altruism by virtue of its mental complexity exists only among human beings (190). But such altruism is always on shaky ground (as game theory has demonstrated) for, in the words of Robert Axelrod, there is “the shadow of the future” – the possibility that one party 53