ASEBL Journal Volume 10, Number 1 | Page 45

ASEBL Journal – Volume 10 Issue 1, January 2014 began to picture and guess the intent and motives of another – cause and effect of the highly developed human brain (and hence the ability, above and beyond social emotions, to make reasoned moral decisions and reflect in conscience on decisions). So it is important to stress (missed by many self-proclaimed old-fashioned philosophers) that reason evolved to solve adaptive problems, not to puzzle out freestanding, challenging abstractions about the truth of the universe. Part four addresses the moral senses. Krebs is clear about how perspective comes into play in any discussion of the moral senses: typically, we do not feel guilt for another’s action and we do not experience moral outrage over our own bad actions. The social behaviors gave rise to duty, ethics arose from norms, and conscience grew from “emotional reactions” witnessing the antisocial action and subsequent punishment of others (203). In other words, rather than saying (as many do) moral sense, Krebs says senses, since it is an approval/disapproval mechanism of feeling and of thought, in part directed inwardly, in part outwardly, sometimes including thoughts and feelings prior to a decision, and sometimes only upon reflection. To complicate this picture, Krebs notes how we can (and do) form moral judgments in other ways (beyond personal/social emotions and group norms) – namely, by another’s rank, accrued deeds, and even overall hygienic appearance. Where is rationality in this type of visceral evaluation? In fact, our moral judgments can be colored by our location (and its relative cleanliness). This, then, is not merely approval/disapproval but an evaluation as to the perceived intrinsic worth of something and how it would (adaptively) help one (or not). Krebs cites a number of researchers here, from Hauser, to Byrne and Whiten, to Haidt, and de Waal. Calling on anthropologist A.P. Fiske, Krebs reports that cross-culturally, human beings categorize social behaviors as “affectionate,” “hierarchical,” “egalitarian,” or “economic,” and while chimpanzees are capable of the first three, only human beings can combine all and especially utilize the fourth (220). Our abilities to cooperate are such that we will alter (even change) our beliefs to do so, and these types of mental adjustments in social interactions would account for the development of theory of mind. Once again deferring to the individual, Krebs notes that while there are universal norms, such norms evolve from the types of moral evaluations individuals decide to make and keep. The origin of social mores is not in the environment per se, but the environment of learning will help spread such mores. So while there are innate (genetic) dispositions that generate a moral culture, that very culture is an essential prop for the maintenance of such norms (unless it is a purely universal norm, such as fairness). Culture depends on how any group has decided to solve an adaptive problem (and hence why the universal notion of sharing will differ in particulars among cultures). In part five, human nature, morality, and new models are covered. Krebs cites research that suggests utilitarian models of morality are cognitively driven whereas deontological models of morality are emotionally driven. But this type of split is only superficial because we originated it: human beings “are naturally disposed to help others . . . [and] to obey rules . . .” (245). Since these tendencies emerge in a social environment, Krebs is keen to recognize and not dismiss social learning – apparently it is another of our adaptive functions. If we turn to biologists such as Eva Jablonka 45