ASEBL Journal Volume 10, Number 1 | Page 46

ASEBL Journal – Volume 10 Issue 1, January 2014 and Marion Lamb we might be able to include in “social learning” organic-related elements such as epigenetics and even transmittable behaviors and symbols. Krebs returns to Kohlberg and, as reluctant as he is, criticizes data that was derived from studies on only male students in a university setting to hypothetical questions – i.e., why-type questions which do not reveal one’s moral grounding but instead become an “intellectual exercise” (265). Krebs cites studies that demonstrate how the reality of a situation draws responses dramatically different from any theoretical question/answer (and even more difference occurs between men and women). Think, for a moment, about all of the ink spilled analyzing over and again Philippa Foot’s runaway tram scenario (and all of its variations, e.g., the footbridge). Ultimately Krebs says that while socia l learning is an important part of our cultural mores it does not account for the origins of moral systems. Staunch evolutionary psychologists such as Leda Cosmides and John Tooby would suggest that different modules are simply part of our evolved brain mechanisms, inherited from our ancestral past, which served adaptive (social) challenges (about, e.g., selfishness and aggression) that increased fitness. Krebs admits that putting together the puzzle about the origins of morality is difficult; since his training was by Kohlberg (in spite of his insistence that he has moved away from him) we can still see his sensitivity to social learning although he places more emphasis on evolution. Some will say that evolutionary studies have nothing substantial to add to the origins of morality, that evolutionary ethics is too theoretical; but the evidence is available and has been studied by too many biologists and psychologists (from Hamilton and Axelrod, to Trivers and Alexander) to ignore. David Haig has gone even further, suggesting, first, the “social gene” and then, later, “intrapersonal reciprocity” (where, despite conflict, internal gene equilibrium is reflected in external social equilibrium). Others might dismiss evolutionary studies altogether, believing that every other part of us (could possibly have) evolved except for our (divine) brain, and that our ancestral environment (whose remnants are evident in other behaviors) has nothing to do with our moral sense. Krebs (and others like him) needs to be commended for his authentic effort, substantial contribution, and honest courage. - Gregory F. Tague ▬ Christopher Boehm. Moral Origins: The Evolution of Virtue, Altruism, and Shame. NY: Basic Books, 2012. 432 pgs. $28.99US Hardcover. ISBN: 9780465020485 Going against the grain of individual selection theories (which posit the emergence of altruism from parental bonds and kin relationships), Christopher Boehm makes a powerful argument for group (social) selection to account for the advent of altruism. Paradoxically, according to Boehm, altruism occurred through negatives: punishment of free-riders and subsequently the fear of public shame (which in turn developed into conscience). Boehm claims our moral origins lie in the adaptive design (its flexibility to rules) of the conscience (away from “fear-based” bullying) and its great concern with maintaining the highest possible personal reputation (176). Drawing from his 46