SotA Anthology 2018-19 | Page 105

of socialisation and not necessarily reason) it is not immutable and is supplemented by the agent’s reflection and reason. In this way, RMS provides the original moral experience required by reflective judgment’s operation in appraising a moral situation, but, RMS in itself does not contradict or cause problems for ethical principles. It is simply a starting point, a resource for the reflective judgment to draw upon initially and itself is subject to the reflective judgment, which subjects it to the cognitive power of the agent for evaluation (Kant, 1987, p.400). In this way, it is not so much that it picks out morally salient features for the judgment, and thus determines what the agent perceives, rather, the judgment utilises and examines RMS and determines what the RMS picks out in a reciprocating relationship (O’Neill, 1989, p.4). The agent initially perceives what they are socialised to, then, the power of the reflective judgment shapes that perception, before determination of what concept a situation should be placed under. I do not believe that this formulation poses any difficulties or problems for principle-based ethical theories and shows the power of judgment being able to deal with the ongoing perception of morally salient features and its role in the genesis of the moral experience used in its operation. This also, I believe, demonstrates where the perceived goodness of moral perception comes from: the accurate recognition of morally salient features is praised due its reflection of the accuracy of the agent’s power of judgment in its reflective capacity of appraisal. This provides a coherent and reconcilable response to the problem of moral perception’s intrinsic moral goodness. The last point I will address is that of moral action that is generated from moral perception prior to ethical principles being invoked. There are several solutions to this problem which can resolve it without causing a contradiction or limit to moral principles. Previously mentioned points also pertain here. That the strategies of judgment operate quite unconsciously is worth examining in this context. Take the example mentioned above whereby moral action is taken via compassion. If the ability to recognise distress is a necessary component of enacting the Kantian maxim of beneficence and helping other people, then the Kantian agent would have failed if they do not act when recognising distress (Herman, 1985, p.423). The reflective power of judgment, in picking out the morally salient features, through the methods described above, recognises the child’s discomfort as morally significant. It is not necessary for the agent to consciously apply the determinative judgment when, in situations as morally clear as in the example, the reflective 105