SotA Anthology 2018-19 | Page 104

previous experience. Further, general maxims of judgment are also brought into operation quite unconsciously. When a scientist approaches an experiment, they don’t need to repeat and memorise certain mantras (as in, the logical ways in which experiments should be conducted. For example, ‘a positive claim requires evidence’. It is simply taken as a given without conscious thought being needed unless it is addressed specifically) to themselves to ensure they are approaching it correctly. These maxims are engrained ways of processing information and ways of thinking that guide appraisals. They may be learnt or modified but their actual operation does not require conscious thought. It is plausible, therefore, that the reflective judgment is capable of identifying morally salient features in ways that fit with our natural experience of moral situations. Once the reflective judgment has appraised the situation of its moral character, the other sphere of judgment, determinant judgment, is then able to invoke the ethical principle (Kant, 1987, p.400). This adequately deals with the objections that an agent may not see morally salient features or recognise them as morally salient in themselves, as reflective judgment has the tools available to it to do these very actions. However, it could be said that such an explanation, while feasible, still doesn’t deal with an important question: that of the origin of the moral experience necessary for the judgment to draw upon. Proponents of moral perception very well might say that while the above is all well and good, the genesis of moral experience, prior to the agent even arriving at ethical principles, is still moral perception. In order to develop a moral system and utilise moral judgment, one requires moral perception in the first place. I intend to offer a formulation of Kantianism that accounts for this foundational moral knowledge. Prior to having moral experience, the agent can draw upon ‘rules of moral salience’ (Herman, 1985, p.418) (from here on, RMS). RMS are part of moral education that allow the agent to pick out features that require moral attention. RMS is informed and shaped by upbringing, reflection and societal values. They determine what the agent initially views as morally significant and provide a practical framework of reference for the agent. Within this framework, the agent can then use the power of reflective and determinant judgment to decide on moral action. RMS can be modified through reflection and education, as the agent matures and develops ethically (Herman, 1985, p. 419). In this formulation, RMS provides the initial bedrock upon which reflective judgment rests, but, due to its arbitrary nature (insofar as it is a product 104