The Journal of Animal Consciousness Vol 1, Issue 2 Vol 1 Issue 2 | Page 6

Introduction Consciousness in animals came to the forefront just a few years ago when the Cambridge Declaration of Consciousness (henceforth, ‘Cambridge Declaration’) was signed in July 2012. It proclaims the support of various scientists that non-human animals (from now on referred to as “animals”) have consciousness and awareness to the degree that humans do. The list of animals includes “all mammals, birds, and many other creatures, including octopuses”; these animals were deemed to have a nervous system capable of consciousness (Safina 2015, p. 23). The research upon which this Declaration was based utilized a materialistic approach, primarily examining and measuring responses within the neurobiological substrates of conscious experience in the animals. The irony is that some of the underlying research that led to the conclusions outlined in the Declaration was based upon experiments conducted upon animals held in captivity, including dolphins.1 The Declaration was seen as rather incredulous by many scientists, and lay people alike, as what it was stating had seemed obvious to many for a number of years.2 We come from a recent philosophical history that tells us animals are non-thinking, soul-less creatures – basically automata – so perhaps this was indeed a bit of a surprise to many people. It has only been since the mid-20th century that sentience has been recognized in animals.3 Yet, according to Duncan, a detailed review of history gives us a different story: at least in mammals there has been an acceptance of sentience for centuries among philosophers such as da Vinci, Shakespeare, Francis Bacon, and others (Duncan 2006). On the other hand, Duncan equates Aristotle with René Descartes when he says “there is a clear line of philosophic argument for non-sentience from Aristotle through Thomas Aquinus [sic] and Rene´ Descartes to Immanuel Kant” (Duncan 2006, p. 12). What is not understood here is that Aristotle said “that only humans had rational souls, while the locomotive souls shared by all animals, human and nonhuman, endowed animals with instincts suited to their successful reproduction and survival”. (Allen and Trestman) [emphasis mine] It was Jeremy Bentham, the English social reformer, who got to the crux of the matter, asking the questions: “The question is not Can they reason? or Can they talk? but Can they suffer?” (Bentham 1823, p. 311) [emphasis original]. Operating on instinct for a significant portion of one’s life does not equate to lack of thinking, feeling, and willing; any animal that can feel suffering is conscious. This history of animals being automata is primarily rooted in the philosophy of René Descartes (1596-1650). It was during the mid-1600s that he introduced via his masterpiece, Meditations, what has come to be known as ‘dualism’. For Descartes, the world was only knowable through the activity of reason. He saw a dichotomy between consciousness and matter, being essentially two different substances that can only be brought into cohesion externally. This is what has become known as the Cartesian Duality, or the mind/body split problem.4 Descartes denied sentience to animals, effectively rendering them ‘reflex machines’. This philosophy held sway among the majority of scholars until the mid-20th century when Donald Griffin argued that animals are conscious much as human beings are in his book, The Question of Animal Awareness (1976, Rockefeller University Press). As discussed more thoroughly in the following section, the ‘discovery’ of consciousness in animals has been seen as a boost to the equine assisted therapy profession. The current state of EAP/L concentrates primarily upon the benefit to the human patient/client. In recent years there has been some acknowledgement of the impact upon the horse in human-centered therapy situations. In this paper I maintain that this acknowledgement does not go far enough when we consider the animal from a phenomenological perspective. From that perspective, I will address the impact to the horse as a result of equine assisted therapy for humans. I will also address some of the potentially negative impacts upon the human patient/ client as a result of the typical analytical view of the horse. Then I conclude with an outline as to a phenomenological and synergistic approach to equine assisted therapy. To do this, I bring in several concepts that are not normally associated with the horse world in general nor with EAP/L specifically. The first major one is to view the horse through the lens of Goethean science with regard to