SotA Anthology 2018-19 | Page 110

moral theory that places the life of the individual above everything else and thus ethical egoism is the moral code that we should accept. Is Rand’s rationale for endorsing ethical egoism as the preferred moral code convincing? If one accepts the deficiencies of altruism that she highlights it would be easy to reach this conclusion. However, on closer inspection Rand seems to present us with a false choice - either altruism or ethical egoism. Whilst Rand is entitled to argue the case against altruism, it does not follow that ethical egoism stands as the only viable alternative. As Rachels explains, if altruism means that we might be required to make sacrifices at any time and for any person then of course ethical egoism looks appealing by comparison. However, to present altruism and ethical egoism as ‘either/or’ is not a reasonable position to take. The common sense view of morality sits between the two extremes and tells us that we ought to balance our interests against those of others - sometimes our interests will take priority and at other times the interests of others will win out. But if we endorse this ‘mix and match’ approach we are not accepting self-interest as the basis for morality. Having suggested that the common sense view of morality sits between egoism and altruism, we need to evaluate whether self-interest might indeed be compatible with common sense morality. By common sense morality we mean obeying certain rules such as ‘do not lie’, ‘do not murder’ or ‘avoid doing harm to others.’ On the face of it these duties appear to be a somewhat random set of rules with no unifying feature. Rachels thinks that ethical egoism might be the one “fundamental principle from which all the rest can be derived” (Rachels, 2018, p.83). Rachels illustrates his point with a number of examples. We often need to rely on people being honest in their dealings with us. However, it is not realistic to expect people to be honest with us if we lie to them. It therefore is in our self-interest to refrain from lying. Similarly, consider the duty not to harm others. Let us suppose that we regularly go about harming others. At best we will find that others are reluctant to do us favours when we need them. At worst our harms may be so severe that we end up in prison. We should therefore conclude that our best interests are served by not harming others. On this basis self-interest seems far from immoral, rather it leads us to a workable theory of morality in which self- interest is the fundamental principle that holds our core duties together. Although this argument is appealing it does not fully establish self- interest as a coherent moral theory. We can accept that under most 110