Popular Culture Review Vol. 3, No. 2, August 1992 | Page 59

What Cartoons Can Teach Us About Language and Learning Clifford Geertz has complained that the "besetting sin of interpretive approaches to anything—literature, dreams, symptoms, culture--is that they tend to resist, or to be permitted to resist, conceptual articulation and thus to escape systematic modes of assessment" (24). Freud, on the contrary, has demonstrated in chapter seven of The Interpretation of Dreams, that it is a subject's very resistance which establishes the credence of a work of interpretation. Of course, we might say Freud’s subject was psychological and Geertz's exegetical. But surely one of the great contributions of Freud is his understanding that the exegetical and the psychological subjects are not as distinct as we would like, and that our very resistance to the equation of the two is an anchor point for further theorization. Resistances, in these terms, would need to be a component of any critical examination of culture per se. Unfortunately, as John Fiske has pointed out, we are not accustomed to think of popular culture as being patterned, in some fashion, according to resistant forces. We prefer to think of culture as an ideological glue adhering our private to our social identity. There is manifested here as well a distrust of theory, since as de Man has demonstrated, any resistance is always a resistance to theory. Or, as Lukacs makes the point even better, "structure, not content, is revolutionary." This distrust of theory is understandable, even unavoidable. There seem to be two primary uses of theoretical discourse in the field of popular culture, and both seem a bit condescending. One theorist wants to make Bugs Bunny say something someone who is not a cartoon has said. For example, "What's up Doc?" becomes Bugs Bunny's rejoinder to Aristotle's notion of a final cause. Another theorist wants to make someone who is not a cartoon character respond to Bugs Bunny's "What's up Doc?": "Machiavelli anticipates that lapine trickster." The assumption behind each of those "theoretical applications to popular culture" is that the profundity of the popular