Mining Mirror February 2018 | Page 33

Business will not, in practice, be zero’. That is, corruption could not be completely eradicated without also burning the house down, although there should be an equilibrium point between anti-corruption and efficiency. This is the realm of economics and organisational studies, of course.  Going beyond Klitgaard’s normative approach, however, the anti-corruption idea shows more fundamental issues. The problem with efforts to curb malfeasance is apparent to the initiated: if leaders – who are the ones charged with the task of adopting and carrying out anti-corruption measures inside their organisations – are already engaged in illegal acts, the anti-corruption drive will not just stop short of the maximum (as Klitgaard’s tenet suggests), but will most likely stop much earlier than that. How early? Although the answer will change from case to case, we can reasonably expect the political will for integrity efforts to cease when they begin to pose a threat to the interests of the leadership.  But let us take a step back, before moving on. Anti-corruption, just as any other government activity, does not only translate into costs. Considering it affects society (we hope in a beneficial way), it also creates benefits for the government in the form of political capital. This capital, when we drop the assumption of a virtuous and devout leadership, explains in theory the reason certain policies are adopted while others are ignored. Not surprisingly, political capital is especially important in democracies, where it can translate directly into votes and power. Therefore, Klitgaard’s notion (of anti-corruption efforts being acceptable just providing productivity can be maintained) could be converted into a more realistic statement: anti-corruption efforts are pursued just only if they are politically profitable for the leadership. The ugly truth Clearly, the obvious conflict between approaches based on political capital and political will is insurmountable when we artificially leave aside the crucial weight of agency and private interests. To reconcile both positions, it is necessary to accept that for an honest government, anti-corruption policies must only be attractive in direct relation to the political capital they can generate. Conversely, for a corrupt government, anti-corruption policies should be avoided in