Military Review English Edition November-December 2014 | Page 109

CRITICAL THINKING compared to those at the paid-professional level, again indicating time is a human invention. Also of note to the interpretivist is that there is a certain irony that an hour of official play time often involves more than three hours for a single game. Football statistics give us the impression of objective fact; hence, predictability. Predictability is the quintessential goal of the logico-scientific paradigm. Measures of player and team performance may give clues as to which teams will make the playoffs. Measures of effectiveness, such as scores at the end of a quarter, half, or game are partially reliable predictors of an overall season victor. However, we cannot imagine looking only at a computer screen with ongoing statistics to fully appreciate what is happening a game. We want to appreciate and emotionally involve ourselves in what is happening on the ground. When viewing the game, we interpret how it is going and realize that strictly monitoring “objective” statistics is not satisfactory. We celebrate (with emotion) when underdogs surprise us by winning games that probability and statistics would deny—and we experience heightened morale (also an emotional state) when the winning team surges. We are aware, outside the conduct of a game, of ongoing, behind-the-scenes, complex emotional tensions among the players, managers, and owners of the teams. These require subjective judgments as to whether the players will be fined, go on strike, be provided disability pensions, be recruited, or be traded to other teams. We interpret how outside interactions might affect the game at hand and the season ahead. Finally, taking ourselves outside our comfort zone, the interpretivist in us contemplates why culture in the United States has created a very different epistemology of football from most of the rest of the world, whose game we Americans call soccer. We should critically wonder why we call our game football at all. Objectively, the ball is kicked far less than it is carried or thrown. With this short allegory, we demonstrate that the reality of professional football may simultaneously be ontologically objective and subjective, that the epistemologies (knowledge structures) of football vary along the logico-scientific—interpretive continuum, and that methods of meaning legitimation in the sport are heterogeneous. Making sense of football strictly from the logico-scientific paradigm would certainly constrain our overall interpretations of its complexity, MILITARY REVIEW  November-December 2014 highlighting the need to derive an aesthetic-subjective appreciation of the game. We learn from this allegory that with complexity there must be a great deal of room for interpretation, a respect for other knowledge forms, and other methods of knowledge formation that are equally important to produce richness in our sensemakings about what we are observing. Indeed, our military sensemakings would become disabling if we were to employ only the logico-scientific paradigm to study the complexity of our recent experiences in Afghanistan, observing the messiness of Syria and Iraq, and in the wake of Russian involvement in the Ukraine. Obviously, such complexity demands even more concoctions of ontological, epistemological, and methodological ingredients than would football. Dual Paradigms Offer Complementary, Critical Perspectives Logico-scientists criticize interpretivists as too speculative, violating such notions as Paul’s and Elder’s “universal intellectual standards” which offer the promise of removing ambiguity and imprecision. These standards suggest only the logico-scientific paradigm provides a legitimate basis for critical reasoning. That is, the military practitioner should seek to remove all subjectivity about the situation at hand; apply a generalizable epistemology of proven tactics, techniques, and procedures expected to work again and again; and use scientific methods to further legitimate those tactics, techniques, and procedures and add new ones (deducing the rigorous application of authoritative practice and inducing so-called lessons learned and best practices into those doctrines). Conversely, interpretivism provides a vehicle to criticize logico-scientism. The interpretive purist sees logico-scientism as a collection of socially constructed objectifications that habitually distort reality.9 As veterans of recent military operations will appreciate, to remove subjectivity, using the intellectual standards suggested by Paul and Elder is inadequate when dealing with befuddling complex situations where subjective appraisals are vitally important. Such confounding situations tend to present themselves at the opposite end of the continua—infusing us with senses of ambiguity, inaccuracy, or imprecision. Equipped only with logico-scientific epistemology, we will hopelessly try 107