International Journal on Criminology Volume 7, Number 2, Spring 2020 | Page 114

Underestimating the Political Dimension in Urban and Geopolitical Violence affiliation based on interaction, 12 i.e. of a subject also being an actor who is capable of 13 acting, understanding, and doing, 14 within the context of a group (from the couple to the state) as defined by the Parsonian model of institutional individualism, 15 and as currently understood for example by social epistemology in studying the degree of naturalness. 16 This epistemological argument will be established as follows: in the light of various examples, we will assess the pertinence of analyzing a particular act or behavior (by a person or structure) in itself, not by simply describing a normative ought. In other words, we will consider a subject as the morphological sign of a political motivation to shape a reality in order to bind it to an affiliation and derive from it a particular status; and to do so irrespective of whether the historic social form in which it is presented varies across different individuals and societies. * I Political Affiliation Formalizes Status Affiliation Yves Sintomer and Marie-Hélène Bacqué use the “key concept” of “disaffiliation” to study “former working-class towns in the Paris area,” specifically Saint-Denis and Aubervilliers (Bacqué and Sintomer 2001, 217). The two authors observe that these neighborhoods must not be studied solely from the perspective of marginalization—with the integration/exclusion binomial in some sense replacing “class conflict” (ibid)—because the populations they study appear 12 Weber (2019 [1921], 338-9): “( ... ) rulership is the chance that specific (or all) commands will be met with obedience on the part of a specifiable group of persons. It is not therefore each and every kind of chance of exercising ‘power’ and ‘influence’ over other people. In this sense, in the individual instance rulership (‘authority’) can also rely on the most varied motives for conformity: from dull habituation to purely purposively rational considerations. Present in every genuine relationship of rule is a specific minimum of willingness to obey, hence an (outward or inner) interest in obedience.” 13 Julien Freund (1967, 37) states that the “specific objective of politics is determined based on the sense of a collective, i.e. it consists of the will of a political unit to preserve its integrity and independence in internal harmony and external security. ( ... ) politics is also the place—but not the only place—where man attempts to give consistency to general and ultimate human ends, such as justice, freedom, happiness, etc.” In The Politics, (IV, 4, 1291a, 15-20) Aristotle takes up the claim in Plato’s Republic that a city is also formed “for the sake of the necessaries of life,” one of which is “the common advantage” (III, 7, 1279a, 10), making it possible to lead a “good life” (I, 2, 1252b, 30). We should also not forget that for Aristotle his Nicomachean Ethics is “in a sense the study of Politics” in that the “Good,” among others, “must be the end of the science of Politics” (I, 3), which he specifies in The Politics (I, 2, 1253a). 14 Baechler 2000. 15 Bourricaud 1977. 16 Bouvier and Conein 2007. 105