International Journal on Criminology Volume 2, Number 1, Spring 2014 | Page 58

International Journal on Criminology finally regain active control over their life as a subject (having been robbed of this by the crime). The victim’s right to recognition ensures that their state as a suffering person is taken into account. This is a fundamental ethical position. Recognition from others is the basis of the victim-subject’s and the perpetrator-subject’s humanity: “The me is awakened by the grace of the you” (Bachelard 1935). According to Axel Honneth (1992), social-recognition relationships are structured around three characteristics pertaining to love (a vector of self-confidence), rights, (a vector of self-respect), and social solidarity (a vector of self-esteem). Recognition is therefore “based on the experience of intersubjectivity [which supposes that] the relationship is more important than the individual” (Guéguen and Malochet 2012). The support of those involved is an essential accompaniment to recognition. Supporting someone means linking oneself to them to go where they go, at the same time as them, and at their pace. It also means empathetic sharing of the sufferings of the protagonists—certainly those of the victim, but also those of the perpetrator. Placed at the center of the process of consideration, the victim is the only person who knows the suffering he or she has experienced; he or she is the only person who knows the direction that needs to be taken, and what the crucial problems that need to be faced are and what his or her needs are to be able to resolve those problems (Rogers 1961). Reparation must be total, full, and effective. It means taking care of oneself and of the other as a victimized person, taking into account the complexity of all that has been suffered. Material compensation is necessary, but it is not enough (see above). Psychological and social reparation, where necessary, must also come into play. Similarly, in criminal proceedings, full participation as an active subject offers both procedural reparation and, once the decision is final, symbolic reparation through naming and separation (of acts and persons). Should it be emphasized that these ethical positions must also benefit the perpetrator, who, however serious his or her acts, is still a person with fundamental human rights, to whom the major procedural principles must also apply? Should it be emphasized that these rights and principles must be shared by the immediate and close communities to which the protagonists belong, as well as more widely by all citizens? If this is not the case, any attempts to restore the social bond will remain wishful thinking. Thanks to the work of victim support practitioners (in the broadest sense) and researchers in victimology, new needs have been identified. These have finally allowed legislators to allocate a “status” to victims of offenses. Thus, in order not to remain little known or unknown, the victim must have free and quick access to the law. All democratic societies must introduce initiatives to provide this. Similarly, obtaining legal aid consolidates the recognition of every victim’s right to the valuable defense of a lawyer. The victim can choose between civil proceedings (an ordinary judge or the crime-victim compensation commission) or criminal proceedings (direct proceedings, an ordinary complaint, or a complaint with a claim for criminal indemnification). Taking civil action offers real guarantees to victims of crimes or serious offenses (the proportionality principle must apply), or their entitled persons. It does this by allowing them either to engage public action (by means of action), or to become a part of it (by means of intervention). Although this is an important right, victims can still struggle to fully exercise it in everyday practices. It is just as important to respect the rights of victims to be received, speak, and 56