Dicta 2013 | Page 54

DICTAeducation Defence of Jurisprudence In Matthew Birchall argues that legal philosophy should be studied ‘actively’. T he study of jurisprudence, or ‘the philosophy of law,’ is split into two main branches: analytical jurisprudence and normative jurisprudence. The former seeks to answer the question ‘what is law?’ through empirical analysis of legal systems and concepts, whereas the latter is concerned with determining what the law ought to be – i.e. what constitutes ‘good’ law. A common student response to these questions, however, is: ‘Why does it matter?’ There are, you may be surprised to hear, those who thoroughly enjoy the subject from the very first lecture, though this would appear to be a minority view. For others it is an acquired taste: something which they learn to appreciate, or at least tolerate. For the rest, jurisprudence is often seen as abstract, impenetrable, and irrelevant to pursuit of a career in the law. It is certainly easy to see why this has become the prevailing view – after all, jurisprudence is not a requisite component of a qualifying law degree, so why not study something of more practical use? Even for those who have decided to read law, with no intention whatsoever of becoming a lawyer, the lack of a ‘correct’ answer to jurisprudential questions may be an intensely frustrating aspect of the subject. This is undoubtedly made worse by the amount of time dedicated to exposing the flaws of each and every theorist’s account of law, with plausible solutions to their shortcomings few and far between. However, whilst these complaints may be understandable from the perspective of the modern student, they overlook the purpose of studying jurisprudence in the first place and therefore ruin any chance of enjoying the subject. The primary goal of studying jurisprudence is not necessarily to find definitive answers to the philosophical questions surrounding law, but rather to explore them and develop a greater understanding of issues. For example, why do people obey the law? Is it due to fear of sanctions for breaching law, as advocated by command theorists like John Austin? Or is H.L.A. Hart’s theory more accurate – that it is due to an acceptance by legal officials of the legitimacy of the legislator combined with public acceptance of the validity of the legal system as a whole that makes individuals feel under an obligation to obey the law? Though the question may seem abstract, it has important ramifications in terms of the efficiency of the criminal justice system. If command theories are accurate, then high incidence of breaking a particular law would seem to indicate that the relevant sanction is not severe enough. However, if other theories, such as Hart’s, are more accurate, then increasing severity of the punishment for breaking a particular law may have negligible impact upon the undesirable behaviour. Moreover, the study of a subject as complex and indeterminate as jurisprudence requires students to develop a solid grasp of the concepts and be able to reflect upon their relative merits, as opposed to learning how to apply law to specific circumstances. Through studying jurisprudence at Bristol, I have found that it provides an excellent opportunity to enhance rational t