ASEBL Journal Volume 13 Issue 1 January 2018 | Page 31

ASEBL Journal – Volume 13 Issue 1, January 201 8 to our definition of what it means to be human and to possess and employ moral sense. I begin and end with quotes from current news articles to try and ground the discussion in individual, “live” responses to the subject at hand, and as a gentle re- minder to readers that necessary participants in the debate over human-directed evolu- tion do not all reside within the bounds of professional academia. A recent BBC news article asked 50 leaders in science, academia, business and gov- ernment for their opinions on the greatest challenges confronting human society. One of the most striking responses came from Joel Garreau, Professor of Law, Culture, and Values at Arizona State University School of law: I can’t tell you how many times I’ve talked to guys working on, oh, something like massively increasing the number and power of mito- chondria in human cells. And I’m like, you know that if you massive- ly increase the amount of energy creation in cells, you’re talking about changing what it means to be human, right? Are you intention- ally trying to create supermen? And the answer every time is “Wow, what a fascinating question, I never thought of that.” (Lufkin, 2017) The quote is, of course, proffered by Garreau in order to shock the reader out of com- placency, and the picture of enthusiastic researchers stepping blindly towards a post- human future is unsettling. This is not to say that the whole biotechnology sector is operating in a completely unreflective manner. Almost all the other people polled in the BBC article who discussed similar issues of genetic technology and human en- hancement stressed the need for “ethical reflection” and discussion to avoid abuse and negative consequences. However, not one suggested a particular method for doing so, or a terminology capable of covering such discussion. Current debates over human enhancement too often fall into polarized, even caricatured stances. Overt or disguised appeals to theological concepts of “natural limits” on human knowledge or human abilities, on the one hand, vie against secular, utilitarian claims of the near-limitless, risk-free advantages of such programs on the other. When we examine claims for or against human genetic enhancement more closely, we invariably find teleological claims standing behind them. For instance, by pursuing human enhancement, we are overstepping our role, our purpose, as humans; we are ‘playing God without possession of divine wisdom or understanding.’ Attempts to surpass human limits, however they may be defined, are not simply hazardous or of uncertain consequences, they are existential errors. Or we claim that the purpose of science, of human society, is simply ‘to better the conditions of human life,’ however that life may be defined, or what might constitute improving it. Even seemingly facile or outrageous claims like ‘we’re developing this technology because we can’ or ‘soon we will be able to transcend the physical body entirely’ conceal teleological impulses. The exercise and increase of our abilities and the pursuit of greater knowledge are as- sumed to be moral goods in themselves and in furtherance of our positive human tendencies to create and to improve ourselves. These teleological claims are, of course, inextricably bound with the general question of the teleology of the human species. What is the purpose of the human species as one species of life among many others on earth? What is our purpose as self- 31