ASEBL Journal Volume 10, Number 1 | Page 58

ASEBL Journal – Volume 10 Issue 1, January 2014 model). Mesoudi spends a good amount of time working over the macro/micro divide. In terms of macroevolution, Mesoudi looks at archaeology and anthropology, and nicely explains phylogenetics in terms of cultural trees, past (e.g., paleoindian projectile points) and present. But this raises (as Mesoudi says) Galton’s problem: in terms of descent with modification in culture, what came first? Darwin’s early critics (e.g., Fleeming Jenkin and even Lord Kelvin) complained of a similar problem: how did natural selection start? Mesoudi goes on to offer an answer (provided in part by the phylogenetic tree). Societies, while culturally distinct, nevertheless share traits, all of which go back to some common ancestor. So while cultural transmission, some argue, is a messy horizontal blending and does not therefore lend itself to a phylogeny, analyses have nevertheless been done (and Mesoudi cites examples). Mesoudi also tackles language and history in terms of macroevolution (in that language and its elements are akin to evolutionary change). As Mesoudi (among others) notes, there are thousands and thousands of languages, which implies different cultural groups, which assumes (as per Richerson and Boyd) cultural group selection. Lab experiments and tests demonstrating cultural transmission are adequately explained, as well as field experiments (much of this covered in two chapters). It is worth noting that Mesoudi cites with authority Judith Rich Harris (as does, elsewhere, Jonathan Haidt) – and why not since their models promote horizontal (group) and not vertical (parental) learning and transmission of information; meantime Jerome Kagan questions Harris’ research, and why not, since his emphasis is on discrete amygdala activity and individual temperament. But Mesoudi’s argument is well taken: learning and cultural evolution may come down to a question of scale, where the parents are but a small part of the larger and more informed group (which is well-stocked with prestige models of skilled workers and expert teachers). In terms of economics, Mesoudi provides interesting examples of cultural evolution (such as irrational behavior in the demise of Polaroid, which developed a digital camera but insisted consumers wanted paper, and how at the turn of the twentieth century there were nearly three hundred tire manufacturers, whittled down by competition to a mere handful by the 1980s). So the model of variation, competition, and inheritance applies. Mesoudi ends by looking at non-human culture (and the differences from human beings). Rats, guppies, rhesus monkeys, female quails, songbirds, octopuses, and honeybees, to name a few species, engage in social (i.e., non-genetic, adaptive) learning. Human beings, however, move from social learning to cultural traditions in and among groups, and so (as Mesoudi points out), human culture is Darwinian since it is cumulative (nearly exact transmission yet descent with modification). The book concludes with an overview that sketches a synthesis of the social sciences using evolutionary methods, i.e., “a potential science of cultural evolution” graphed alongside biological evolution. Mesoudi’s book is highly-recommended for students of the humanities since it convincingly proves the biological evolution behind culture. No doubt biologists and social scientists will find much to consider in the book as well, and one could see how well this text would suit a course on the subjects of culture and evolution. - Gregory F. Tague ▬ 58