ASEBL Journal Volume 10, Number 1 | Page 14

ASEBL Journal – Volume 10 Issue 1, January 2014 consciousness that is the foundation for the ethical power of literature. All authors make use of this power, but certain authors take advantage of it more than others. I contend that one of the reasons for the success of Dostoevsky is that he uses this universal mechanism more effectively than many other authors. To understand how narrative is able to change us through consciousness, it is important to keep in mind the nature of consciousness. Mind and brain are not two different things. Consciousness is not a separate substance from the brain; it is a product of what the brain does, even if the exact process is not fully understood. Consciousness is affected by injury to the brain: a stroke can knock out our ability to be conscious of highly specific things such as color, movement or even a full half of our visual field. Even more bizarrely, people with “blindsight” can lose the ability to see, yet still be somewhat conscious of what is before their eyes.5 Cutting the connection between the hemispheres of the brain can result in a limited splitting of consciousness, each hemisphere aware of a separate half of the visual field. The variety and specificity of these possible deficits goes to show that consciousness is part of what the brain does and that the unified, seamless thing we call consciousness is really the end result of many separate processes, all focused on highly specific inputs that are integrated together. These deficits show that the brain does not behave like the old science fiction cliché of the brain in a jar. While mental functions are localized in the brain, the brain is part of the body and is connected with it.6 The body affects the brain and vice versa. It should come as no surprise that experiences that have physical effects in addition to intellectual will leave a deeper mark on our psyche. The question it leaves is why that is the case, and how something as airy as “changing who we are” (even slightly) can be instantiated physically. Consciousness, I contend, is an important aspect of the relationship between the self and other because it is where the physical and the mental, the outward and the inward, meet; it is the source of lived experience and thus where it can become part of who we are in a deeper way than, for instance, memory or imitation allow. It also allows for the analysis of the subjective experience of a text, its fundamental aspect for a reader. Over the last decade or two we have begun (but only begun) to understand what are called the neur(on)al correlates of consciousness.7 This basis is useful in understanding how we internalize what we take from our environments, including virtual environments. The scientific study of consciousness is one of the most active cottage industries in science, at least judging by the barrage of books that have come out on the topic in the last decade or so.8 Of all the approaches to consciousness,9 the most relevant to the processing of the arts appears to be that of Antonio Damasio. For Damasio, consciousness as we generally think of it is the last step in a long process. At the base of this process is what he calls the “protoself,” on top of which is placed “core consciousness.” The protoself is essentially an unconscious neural map of a person’s physical state at a given instant. As we go about our daily lives, the brain produces a continually-updated map of the body. In addition, it also maps all the objects and people we come into contact with. These various maps are the first level of consciousness. On the next level, the brain produces a map of the relationship between the protoself and non-self objects or people. Core consciousness is a result of this 14